Jeremy H. Howick
The Philosophy of Evidence-based Medicine (eBook, ePUB)
53,99 €
53,99 €
inkl. MwSt.
Sofort per Download lieferbar
0 °P sammeln
53,99 €
Als Download kaufen
53,99 €
inkl. MwSt.
Sofort per Download lieferbar
0 °P sammeln
Jetzt verschenken
Alle Infos zum eBook verschenken
53,99 €
inkl. MwSt.
Sofort per Download lieferbar
Alle Infos zum eBook verschenken
0 °P sammeln
Jeremy H. Howick
The Philosophy of Evidence-based Medicine (eBook, ePUB)
- Format: ePub
- Merkliste
- Auf die Merkliste
- Bewerten Bewerten
- Teilen
- Produkt teilen
- Produkterinnerung
- Produkterinnerung
Bitte loggen Sie sich zunächst in Ihr Kundenkonto ein oder registrieren Sie sich bei
bücher.de, um das eBook-Abo tolino select nutzen zu können.
Hier können Sie sich einloggen
Hier können Sie sich einloggen
Sie sind bereits eingeloggt. Klicken Sie auf 2. tolino select Abo, um fortzufahren.
Bitte loggen Sie sich zunächst in Ihr Kundenkonto ein oder registrieren Sie sich bei bücher.de, um das eBook-Abo tolino select nutzen zu können.
Evidence-based medicine (EBM) has become a required element of clinical practice, but it is critical for the healthcare community to understand the ongoing controversy surrounding EBM. Seeking to address questions raised by critics, The Philosophy of Evidence-based Medicine challenges the over dependency of EBM on randomized controlled trials. This book also explores EBM methodology and its relationship with other approaches used in medicine.
- Geräte: eReader
- mit Kopierschutz
- eBook Hilfe
- Größe: 2.24MB
Andere Kunden interessierten sich auch für
- Evidence-Based Geriatric Medicine (eBook, ePUB)55,99 €
- Carl HeneghanEvidence-Based Medicine Toolkit (eBook, ePUB)27,99 €
- Trisha GreenhalghHow to Implement Evidence-Based Healthcare (eBook, ePUB)33,99 €
- Evidence-based Gastroenterology and Hepatology (eBook, ePUB)262,99 €
- Evidence-Based Dermatology (eBook, ePUB)301,99 €
- Evidence-Based Chronic Pain Management (eBook, ePUB)183,99 €
- Evidence-Based Pediatric Oncology (eBook, ePUB)114,99 €
-
-
-
Evidence-based medicine (EBM) has become a required element of clinical practice, but it is critical for the healthcare community to understand the ongoing controversy surrounding EBM. Seeking to address questions raised by critics, The Philosophy of Evidence-based Medicine challenges the over dependency of EBM on randomized controlled trials. This book also explores EBM methodology and its relationship with other approaches used in medicine.
Dieser Download kann aus rechtlichen Gründen nur mit Rechnungsadresse in A, B, BG, CY, CZ, D, DK, EW, E, FIN, F, GR, HR, H, IRL, I, LT, L, LR, M, NL, PL, P, R, S, SLO, SK ausgeliefert werden.
Produktdetails
- Produktdetails
- Verlag: John Wiley & Sons
- Seitenzahl: 248
- Erscheinungstermin: 24. Februar 2011
- Englisch
- ISBN-13: 9781444342666
- Artikelnr.: 38306553
- Verlag: John Wiley & Sons
- Seitenzahl: 248
- Erscheinungstermin: 24. Februar 2011
- Englisch
- ISBN-13: 9781444342666
- Artikelnr.: 38306553
- Herstellerkennzeichnung Die Herstellerinformationen sind derzeit nicht verfügbar.
Jeremy Howick PhD Centre for Evidence-Based Medicine, Department of Primary Care, University of Oxford, UK
Acknowledgments.
Foreword.
Preface.
Part I: Introduction.
1 The philosophy of evidence-based medicine.
1.1 What on earth was medicine based on before evidence-based medicine?
1.2 Scope of the book.
1.3 How the claims of EBM will be examined.
1.4 Structure of what is to come.
2 What is EBM?
2.1 EBM as a self-proclaimed Kuhnian paradigm.
2.2 The motivation for the birth of EBM: a sketch.
2.3 Original definition of EBM.
2.4 Reaction to criticism of the EBM system of evidence: more subtle, more
or less the same.
3 What is good evidence for a clinical decision?
3.1 Introduction.
3.2 Evidence for clinical effectiveness.
3.3 Strong evidence tells us what?
Part II: Do randomization, double masking, and placebo controls rule out
more confounding factors than their alternatives?
4 Ruling out plausible rival hypotheses and confounding factors: a method.
5 Resolving the paradox of effectiveness: when do observational studies
offer the same degree of evidential support as randomized trials?
5.1 The paradox of effectiveness.
5.2 Observational studies: defi nition and problems.
5.3 Randomized trials to the rescue.
5.4 Defending the EBM view that randomized trials provide better evidence
than observational studies.
5.5 Overcoming the paradox of effectiveness.
5.6 Conclusion: a more subtle way to distinguish between high- and
low-quality comparative clinical studies.
Appendix 1: types of restricted randomization.
Appendix 2: Worrall's arguments that randomization is required for
classical hypothesis testing and establishing probabilistic causes.
6 Questioning double blinding as a universal methodological virtue of
clinical trials: resolving the Philip's paradox.
6.1 The problems with double masking as a requirement for clinical trial
validity.
6.2 The many faces of double masking: clarifying the terminology.
6.3 Confounders that arise from participant and caregiver knowledge.
6.4 The importance of successful double masking.
6.5 One (and a half) solutions to the Philip's paradox.
6.6 The full solution to the Philip's paradox: challenging the view that
double masking rules out confounding factors when treatments are evidently
dramatic.
6.7 Double masking is valuable unless the treatment effects are evidently
dramatic, hence the Philip's paradox does not arise.
7 Placebo controls: problematic and misleading baseline measures of
effectiveness.
7.1 The need to control the placebo.
7.2 Legitimate placebo controls.
7.3 How placebo controls often violate the fi rst condition for legitimacy.
7.4 How placebo controls often violate the second condition for legitimacy.
7.5 Special problem for constructing placebos for complex treatments: case
studies of exercise and acupuncture.
7.6 Summary and solution to the problem with illegitimate placebo controls.
8 Questioning the methodological superiority of "placebo" over "active"
controlled trials.
8.1 Epistemological foundations of the ethical debate over the use of
placebo-controlled trials.
8.2 Problems with the assay sensitivity arguments against ACTs.
8.3 Problems with the fi rst assay sensitivity argument against ACTs.
8.4 The second assay sensitivity argument.
8.5 Challenging the view that PCTs provide a measure of absolute effect
size.
8.6 Questioning the claim that PCTs require smaller sample sizes.
8.7 Conclusion: a reassessment of the relative methodological quality of
PCTs.
Appendix: more detailed explanation of why the second assay sensitivity
argument fails.
Part III: Examining the paradox that traditional roles for mechanistic
reasoning and expert judgment have been up-ended by EBM.
9 Transition to Part III.
9.1 Summary of Part II.
9.2 Introduction to Part III.
10 A qualifi ed defence of the EBM stance on mechanistic reasoning.
10.1 A tension between proponents of mechanistic reasoning and EBM views.
10.2 Clarifying the terminology: comparative clinical studies, mechanisms,
and mechanistic reasoning.
10.3 Why the strong view that mechanistic reasoning is necessary to
establish causal claims is mistaken.
10.4 Two epistemological problems with mechanistic reasoning.
10.5 Why EBM proponents should allow a more prominent role for high-quality
(valid and based on "complete" mechanisms) mechanistic reasoning in their
evidence hierarchies.
10.6 Mechanisms and other roles in clinical medicine.
10.7 Recommending a (slightly) more important role for mechanistic
reasoning in the EBM system.
Appendix: cases where mechanistic reasoning led to the adoption of
therapies that were either useless or harmful according to well-conducted
clinical research.
11 Knowledge that versus knowledge how: situating the EBM position on
expert clinical judgment.
11.1 Controversies surrounding the EBM stance on expert clinical judgement.
11.2 General clinical judgment belongs at the bottom of (or off) the
hierarchy of evidence.
11.3 Individual clinical judgment also belongs at the bottom of the
hierarchy.
11.4 The equally important non-evidential roles of expertise.
11.5 Conclusion.
Part IV: Conclusions.
12 Moving EBM forward.
12.1 Summary of fi ndings: the EBM philosophy is acceptable, but. . ..
12.2 Two new frontiers for EBM.
References.
Index.
Foreword.
Preface.
Part I: Introduction.
1 The philosophy of evidence-based medicine.
1.1 What on earth was medicine based on before evidence-based medicine?
1.2 Scope of the book.
1.3 How the claims of EBM will be examined.
1.4 Structure of what is to come.
2 What is EBM?
2.1 EBM as a self-proclaimed Kuhnian paradigm.
2.2 The motivation for the birth of EBM: a sketch.
2.3 Original definition of EBM.
2.4 Reaction to criticism of the EBM system of evidence: more subtle, more
or less the same.
3 What is good evidence for a clinical decision?
3.1 Introduction.
3.2 Evidence for clinical effectiveness.
3.3 Strong evidence tells us what?
Part II: Do randomization, double masking, and placebo controls rule out
more confounding factors than their alternatives?
4 Ruling out plausible rival hypotheses and confounding factors: a method.
5 Resolving the paradox of effectiveness: when do observational studies
offer the same degree of evidential support as randomized trials?
5.1 The paradox of effectiveness.
5.2 Observational studies: defi nition and problems.
5.3 Randomized trials to the rescue.
5.4 Defending the EBM view that randomized trials provide better evidence
than observational studies.
5.5 Overcoming the paradox of effectiveness.
5.6 Conclusion: a more subtle way to distinguish between high- and
low-quality comparative clinical studies.
Appendix 1: types of restricted randomization.
Appendix 2: Worrall's arguments that randomization is required for
classical hypothesis testing and establishing probabilistic causes.
6 Questioning double blinding as a universal methodological virtue of
clinical trials: resolving the Philip's paradox.
6.1 The problems with double masking as a requirement for clinical trial
validity.
6.2 The many faces of double masking: clarifying the terminology.
6.3 Confounders that arise from participant and caregiver knowledge.
6.4 The importance of successful double masking.
6.5 One (and a half) solutions to the Philip's paradox.
6.6 The full solution to the Philip's paradox: challenging the view that
double masking rules out confounding factors when treatments are evidently
dramatic.
6.7 Double masking is valuable unless the treatment effects are evidently
dramatic, hence the Philip's paradox does not arise.
7 Placebo controls: problematic and misleading baseline measures of
effectiveness.
7.1 The need to control the placebo.
7.2 Legitimate placebo controls.
7.3 How placebo controls often violate the fi rst condition for legitimacy.
7.4 How placebo controls often violate the second condition for legitimacy.
7.5 Special problem for constructing placebos for complex treatments: case
studies of exercise and acupuncture.
7.6 Summary and solution to the problem with illegitimate placebo controls.
8 Questioning the methodological superiority of "placebo" over "active"
controlled trials.
8.1 Epistemological foundations of the ethical debate over the use of
placebo-controlled trials.
8.2 Problems with the assay sensitivity arguments against ACTs.
8.3 Problems with the fi rst assay sensitivity argument against ACTs.
8.4 The second assay sensitivity argument.
8.5 Challenging the view that PCTs provide a measure of absolute effect
size.
8.6 Questioning the claim that PCTs require smaller sample sizes.
8.7 Conclusion: a reassessment of the relative methodological quality of
PCTs.
Appendix: more detailed explanation of why the second assay sensitivity
argument fails.
Part III: Examining the paradox that traditional roles for mechanistic
reasoning and expert judgment have been up-ended by EBM.
9 Transition to Part III.
9.1 Summary of Part II.
9.2 Introduction to Part III.
10 A qualifi ed defence of the EBM stance on mechanistic reasoning.
10.1 A tension between proponents of mechanistic reasoning and EBM views.
10.2 Clarifying the terminology: comparative clinical studies, mechanisms,
and mechanistic reasoning.
10.3 Why the strong view that mechanistic reasoning is necessary to
establish causal claims is mistaken.
10.4 Two epistemological problems with mechanistic reasoning.
10.5 Why EBM proponents should allow a more prominent role for high-quality
(valid and based on "complete" mechanisms) mechanistic reasoning in their
evidence hierarchies.
10.6 Mechanisms and other roles in clinical medicine.
10.7 Recommending a (slightly) more important role for mechanistic
reasoning in the EBM system.
Appendix: cases where mechanistic reasoning led to the adoption of
therapies that were either useless or harmful according to well-conducted
clinical research.
11 Knowledge that versus knowledge how: situating the EBM position on
expert clinical judgment.
11.1 Controversies surrounding the EBM stance on expert clinical judgement.
11.2 General clinical judgment belongs at the bottom of (or off) the
hierarchy of evidence.
11.3 Individual clinical judgment also belongs at the bottom of the
hierarchy.
11.4 The equally important non-evidential roles of expertise.
11.5 Conclusion.
Part IV: Conclusions.
12 Moving EBM forward.
12.1 Summary of fi ndings: the EBM philosophy is acceptable, but. . ..
12.2 Two new frontiers for EBM.
References.
Index.
Acknowledgments.
Foreword.
Preface.
Part I: Introduction.
1 The philosophy of evidence-based medicine.
1.1 What on earth was medicine based on before evidence-based medicine?
1.2 Scope of the book.
1.3 How the claims of EBM will be examined.
1.4 Structure of what is to come.
2 What is EBM?
2.1 EBM as a self-proclaimed Kuhnian paradigm.
2.2 The motivation for the birth of EBM: a sketch.
2.3 Original definition of EBM.
2.4 Reaction to criticism of the EBM system of evidence: more subtle, more
or less the same.
3 What is good evidence for a clinical decision?
3.1 Introduction.
3.2 Evidence for clinical effectiveness.
3.3 Strong evidence tells us what?
Part II: Do randomization, double masking, and placebo controls rule out
more confounding factors than their alternatives?
4 Ruling out plausible rival hypotheses and confounding factors: a method.
5 Resolving the paradox of effectiveness: when do observational studies
offer the same degree of evidential support as randomized trials?
5.1 The paradox of effectiveness.
5.2 Observational studies: defi nition and problems.
5.3 Randomized trials to the rescue.
5.4 Defending the EBM view that randomized trials provide better evidence
than observational studies.
5.5 Overcoming the paradox of effectiveness.
5.6 Conclusion: a more subtle way to distinguish between high- and
low-quality comparative clinical studies.
Appendix 1: types of restricted randomization.
Appendix 2: Worrall's arguments that randomization is required for
classical hypothesis testing and establishing probabilistic causes.
6 Questioning double blinding as a universal methodological virtue of
clinical trials: resolving the Philip's paradox.
6.1 The problems with double masking as a requirement for clinical trial
validity.
6.2 The many faces of double masking: clarifying the terminology.
6.3 Confounders that arise from participant and caregiver knowledge.
6.4 The importance of successful double masking.
6.5 One (and a half) solutions to the Philip's paradox.
6.6 The full solution to the Philip's paradox: challenging the view that
double masking rules out confounding factors when treatments are evidently
dramatic.
6.7 Double masking is valuable unless the treatment effects are evidently
dramatic, hence the Philip's paradox does not arise.
7 Placebo controls: problematic and misleading baseline measures of
effectiveness.
7.1 The need to control the placebo.
7.2 Legitimate placebo controls.
7.3 How placebo controls often violate the fi rst condition for legitimacy.
7.4 How placebo controls often violate the second condition for legitimacy.
7.5 Special problem for constructing placebos for complex treatments: case
studies of exercise and acupuncture.
7.6 Summary and solution to the problem with illegitimate placebo controls.
8 Questioning the methodological superiority of "placebo" over "active"
controlled trials.
8.1 Epistemological foundations of the ethical debate over the use of
placebo-controlled trials.
8.2 Problems with the assay sensitivity arguments against ACTs.
8.3 Problems with the fi rst assay sensitivity argument against ACTs.
8.4 The second assay sensitivity argument.
8.5 Challenging the view that PCTs provide a measure of absolute effect
size.
8.6 Questioning the claim that PCTs require smaller sample sizes.
8.7 Conclusion: a reassessment of the relative methodological quality of
PCTs.
Appendix: more detailed explanation of why the second assay sensitivity
argument fails.
Part III: Examining the paradox that traditional roles for mechanistic
reasoning and expert judgment have been up-ended by EBM.
9 Transition to Part III.
9.1 Summary of Part II.
9.2 Introduction to Part III.
10 A qualifi ed defence of the EBM stance on mechanistic reasoning.
10.1 A tension between proponents of mechanistic reasoning and EBM views.
10.2 Clarifying the terminology: comparative clinical studies, mechanisms,
and mechanistic reasoning.
10.3 Why the strong view that mechanistic reasoning is necessary to
establish causal claims is mistaken.
10.4 Two epistemological problems with mechanistic reasoning.
10.5 Why EBM proponents should allow a more prominent role for high-quality
(valid and based on "complete" mechanisms) mechanistic reasoning in their
evidence hierarchies.
10.6 Mechanisms and other roles in clinical medicine.
10.7 Recommending a (slightly) more important role for mechanistic
reasoning in the EBM system.
Appendix: cases where mechanistic reasoning led to the adoption of
therapies that were either useless or harmful according to well-conducted
clinical research.
11 Knowledge that versus knowledge how: situating the EBM position on
expert clinical judgment.
11.1 Controversies surrounding the EBM stance on expert clinical judgement.
11.2 General clinical judgment belongs at the bottom of (or off) the
hierarchy of evidence.
11.3 Individual clinical judgment also belongs at the bottom of the
hierarchy.
11.4 The equally important non-evidential roles of expertise.
11.5 Conclusion.
Part IV: Conclusions.
12 Moving EBM forward.
12.1 Summary of fi ndings: the EBM philosophy is acceptable, but. . ..
12.2 Two new frontiers for EBM.
References.
Index.
Foreword.
Preface.
Part I: Introduction.
1 The philosophy of evidence-based medicine.
1.1 What on earth was medicine based on before evidence-based medicine?
1.2 Scope of the book.
1.3 How the claims of EBM will be examined.
1.4 Structure of what is to come.
2 What is EBM?
2.1 EBM as a self-proclaimed Kuhnian paradigm.
2.2 The motivation for the birth of EBM: a sketch.
2.3 Original definition of EBM.
2.4 Reaction to criticism of the EBM system of evidence: more subtle, more
or less the same.
3 What is good evidence for a clinical decision?
3.1 Introduction.
3.2 Evidence for clinical effectiveness.
3.3 Strong evidence tells us what?
Part II: Do randomization, double masking, and placebo controls rule out
more confounding factors than their alternatives?
4 Ruling out plausible rival hypotheses and confounding factors: a method.
5 Resolving the paradox of effectiveness: when do observational studies
offer the same degree of evidential support as randomized trials?
5.1 The paradox of effectiveness.
5.2 Observational studies: defi nition and problems.
5.3 Randomized trials to the rescue.
5.4 Defending the EBM view that randomized trials provide better evidence
than observational studies.
5.5 Overcoming the paradox of effectiveness.
5.6 Conclusion: a more subtle way to distinguish between high- and
low-quality comparative clinical studies.
Appendix 1: types of restricted randomization.
Appendix 2: Worrall's arguments that randomization is required for
classical hypothesis testing and establishing probabilistic causes.
6 Questioning double blinding as a universal methodological virtue of
clinical trials: resolving the Philip's paradox.
6.1 The problems with double masking as a requirement for clinical trial
validity.
6.2 The many faces of double masking: clarifying the terminology.
6.3 Confounders that arise from participant and caregiver knowledge.
6.4 The importance of successful double masking.
6.5 One (and a half) solutions to the Philip's paradox.
6.6 The full solution to the Philip's paradox: challenging the view that
double masking rules out confounding factors when treatments are evidently
dramatic.
6.7 Double masking is valuable unless the treatment effects are evidently
dramatic, hence the Philip's paradox does not arise.
7 Placebo controls: problematic and misleading baseline measures of
effectiveness.
7.1 The need to control the placebo.
7.2 Legitimate placebo controls.
7.3 How placebo controls often violate the fi rst condition for legitimacy.
7.4 How placebo controls often violate the second condition for legitimacy.
7.5 Special problem for constructing placebos for complex treatments: case
studies of exercise and acupuncture.
7.6 Summary and solution to the problem with illegitimate placebo controls.
8 Questioning the methodological superiority of "placebo" over "active"
controlled trials.
8.1 Epistemological foundations of the ethical debate over the use of
placebo-controlled trials.
8.2 Problems with the assay sensitivity arguments against ACTs.
8.3 Problems with the fi rst assay sensitivity argument against ACTs.
8.4 The second assay sensitivity argument.
8.5 Challenging the view that PCTs provide a measure of absolute effect
size.
8.6 Questioning the claim that PCTs require smaller sample sizes.
8.7 Conclusion: a reassessment of the relative methodological quality of
PCTs.
Appendix: more detailed explanation of why the second assay sensitivity
argument fails.
Part III: Examining the paradox that traditional roles for mechanistic
reasoning and expert judgment have been up-ended by EBM.
9 Transition to Part III.
9.1 Summary of Part II.
9.2 Introduction to Part III.
10 A qualifi ed defence of the EBM stance on mechanistic reasoning.
10.1 A tension between proponents of mechanistic reasoning and EBM views.
10.2 Clarifying the terminology: comparative clinical studies, mechanisms,
and mechanistic reasoning.
10.3 Why the strong view that mechanistic reasoning is necessary to
establish causal claims is mistaken.
10.4 Two epistemological problems with mechanistic reasoning.
10.5 Why EBM proponents should allow a more prominent role for high-quality
(valid and based on "complete" mechanisms) mechanistic reasoning in their
evidence hierarchies.
10.6 Mechanisms and other roles in clinical medicine.
10.7 Recommending a (slightly) more important role for mechanistic
reasoning in the EBM system.
Appendix: cases where mechanistic reasoning led to the adoption of
therapies that were either useless or harmful according to well-conducted
clinical research.
11 Knowledge that versus knowledge how: situating the EBM position on
expert clinical judgment.
11.1 Controversies surrounding the EBM stance on expert clinical judgement.
11.2 General clinical judgment belongs at the bottom of (or off) the
hierarchy of evidence.
11.3 Individual clinical judgment also belongs at the bottom of the
hierarchy.
11.4 The equally important non-evidential roles of expertise.
11.5 Conclusion.
Part IV: Conclusions.
12 Moving EBM forward.
12.1 Summary of fi ndings: the EBM philosophy is acceptable, but. . ..
12.2 Two new frontiers for EBM.
References.
Index.